Some philosophers want the advantage of making this distinction as
well as the benefit of having an acceptable decision procedure. Peter
Railton, for example, makes the distinction and says that it is `an
empirical question (though not an easy one) which modes of decision
making should be employed and when'. I
shall argue that the cost of act utilitarianism's impracticability is
higher than mere difficulty in deciding which decision procedure to
employ. A consequence of act utilitarianism's impracticability is
that, if act utilitarianism were true, we would have inadequate
reason to believe that our moral decisions were correct. I now turn
to this revised impracticability argument.
In my defence of this argument I will focus on premises (1) and (2). Premise (3) seems reasonable and I will have nothing to say about it. After my defence of the premises, I will consider a general objection to the argument. I will start by explaining some notions that I employ. In particular, I should say what I take act utilitarianism to be and what an ethicaal decision procedure is, what makes one practicable and when one is validated.
My argument is intended to apply to a suite of act utilitarian
theories. All of the relevant theories connect the moral
permissibility of acts with their utility. They differ, however, in
their views about what determines the utility of an act. For example,
some propose that the utility of an act is a function of a number of
discrete features, while others say that it is a function only of the
welfare or happiness it produces.
Another feature common to this suite of views is their proposal that
objective or actual utility, not subjective or expected utility, is
the relevant utility. Indeed, a way to avoid the criticism that I am
leveling against act utilitarianism, though not one without its own
costs, is to adopt a different utilitarian theory, one that says that
agents are morally permitted to perform an action just in case it is
reasonable to believe that it will have at least as good consequences
as any of its alternatives.
The utilitarian views that I have in mind are also impersonal. What
matters is the amount of utility (aggregate, average, etc.), not who
acts or benefits from an act.
I characterize this suite of views, AU, as follows:
In general, a decision procedure is a method for determining an answer to questions for which it is a decision procedure. In particular, an ethical decision procedure (EDP) gives an answer about the moral permissibility of an act. An EDP is practicable when we are able to use it. It need not be easy to use, nor must it be possible to use it in extraordinary situations. But in ordinary situations, even if it takes considerable effort, we must be able to apply the method. Applying it must be practically possible. An EDP is validated when we have good reason to believe that it gives the correct answer to questions for which it is a decision procedure. Of course, this does not mean that we have to be certain that it gives the correct answer. That would be to require too much. But we must have a reasonable amount of evidence that it is accurate.
With these preliminaries out of the way, I can turn to the defence of premise (1).
There are at least three approaches that can be used to support the
claim that AU is impracticable as an EDP. The first i to argue
that, since it is impossible to determine uniquely our alternatives at
a time (there is no unique set of alternatives), it is impossible to
arrive at a unique determination of the relative utilities of our
alternatives. The second relies on the view that it is practically
impossible to determine all of the consequences of our alternatives
(even if we can determine what these alternatives are). The third
approach is to argue that we cannot determine the relative utilities,
or values, of alternatives, even of those whose consequences we know.
Although I believe that each approach could be fruitful, I will
concentrate on the second.
Keep in mind that the relevant claim is not that it is merely very
difficult to determine all of the consequences of our alternatives, but
that it is practically impossible to do so.
The practical impossibility of ascertaining the consequences of our
alternatives results, largely, from the transitivity of causation.
Since causation is transitive, every event that succeeds an act and is
in a causal chain with that act is a consequence of that act. Most
acts are parts of a very large number of causal chains and these
causal chains can go on indefinitely. Consequently, most acts have an
abundance of consequences and each consequence can be relevant to the
utility of the act. Jonathan Bennett seems to recognize this when he
says, `I sometimes feel oppressed by the thought that so much of the
world's future history will have been caused by (among other things)
my conduct ...'.
The better to see just how difficult it is to determine the consequences of acts and, therefore, their utilities, let us consider a couple of acts, their alternatives and their consequences. Let us consider a famous act, which we would suppose to have a lot of significant consequences, and a less famous act. Considering these two examples does not, of course, establish that we cannot determine the consequences of our actions. It merely displays some difficulties encountered in trying to do so. Indeed, anyone providing a list of all of the consequences of some act would show, conclusively, that it is not practically impossible to do so.
The famous act is Socrates' drinking of the hemlock. Can we ascertain all of the consequences of this actual act? I believe not. Surely no one will claim actually to have done so. Of course we can ascertain some of them, although it may be difficult to say how much any event is a consequence of Socrates' act. For instance, it is hard to see how Plato would have produced the Crito if Socrates had not drunk the hemlock. Even if he had, it is hard to see how it would have been as important. This, however, is just the beginning of the consequences. Indeed, since Socrates' act is still being discussed, there is very little reason to believe that it will not go on having important consequences.
If we cannot ascertain all of the consequences of Socrates' drinking of the hemlock, we surely cannot ascertain what the consequences would have been had he not done so. For example, would all of philosophy consist of footnotes to Plato? The difficulties in determining the consequences of Socrates' alternatives make it impossible for us to ascertain their utilities (relative or absolute). The impossibility is not conceptual or metaphysical, merely practical.
We encounter similar problems with more prosaic acts. This morning I put some change in the right-hand pocket of my trousers. Can I ascertain the consequences of what I actually did? I do not even know when it stops having consequences. It and its alternatives may not have very significant consequences, but I do not believe that we can ascertain them, or that we can discover their relative utilities. Remember that according to AU the significance of an act does not, in itself, determine the permissibility of an act; instead, it is the relative utility of the act that does so. Consequently, little differences between acts of little significance can make a moral difference.
It is important to note that I am not committed to saying that for all we know, any seemingly unimportant act may have titanic consequences. There may be some situations whose very nature may give us good reason to think that any act done will be insignificant in the larger scheme of things. I do not have strong views about whether this is so. However, I do believe that if we have some alternatives in such situations we cannot be justified in thinking of any of these alternatives that doing it will bring about at least as much utility as any of the others. Nor do I believe that, in situations where there may be titanic consequences, we can be justified in believing of any act that it will have at least as much utility as its alternatives.
By considering the nature of causality, we should conclude that it is
practically impossible to ascertain all of the consequences of any
action.
If AU, considered as a decision procedure, were practicable, but merely difficult to use, then it could be employed in validating EDPs that were easier to use. However, since it is not, it cannot. Is there some other way to validate an EDP for AU? We cannot test an EDP for AU directly, by considering what an act's actual consequences will be. This is because we cannot ascertain all of an act's remote consequences. So, if we are to be able to validate an EDP for AU, it must be that we can be justified in discounting the remote consequences of acts. I shall now argue that we cannot be justified in discounting remote consequences and hence that AU cannot have a validated EDP.
What reasons could one give for thinking that these remote consequences can be discounted?
As far as I can tell, there are three ways in which one might attempt to justify the total discounting of remote consequences. The first is to claim that remote consequences are insignificant. The second is to claim that the remote consequences of an act must have the same relative utility as its near consequences. And the third is to claim that remote consequences even out so that any good remote consequence is matched by an equally bad remote consequence.
These can be thought of as empirical claims, supported by an examination of a number of cases, as conceptual claims about the relationship between events, time and utility, or as assumptions. Regardless of how they are understood, we have little reason to accept them. Since they are most reasonably taken to be empirical claims, let us first decide whether we have good empirical evidence for them.
The empirical evidence needed to support any one of these claims can be obtained only by examining a number of cases to see what the relationship is between near and remote consequences. There is a major obstacle to meeting this requirement: most, if not all, acts are still having effects. Since we are attempting to justify the discounting of remote effects, we cannot assume that the effects more distant than now are not relevant. Consequently, we have a paucity of cases to examine and it is hard to see how we can test these claims.
Perhaps it would be good enough to test the claims partially. If we
look at a number of acts performed long ago and find that one of the
claims has held over a relatively long period of time, then we might
have some justification for accepting it. G.E. Moore suggests
something like this. He accepts the need for discounting future
consequences, suggests that they are insignificant because `whatever
action we now adopt, ``it will be all the same a hundred years
hence''' and says that `this might, perhaps, be shewn to be
true, by an investigation of the manner in which the effects of any
particular event become neutralised by lapse of time'. Moore does
not report the results of such an investigation, which is not
surprising given the difficulties in determining the consequences of
actions. Unfortunately, however, Moore simply assumes that his claim
is true and argues for substantive normative conclusions despite his
statement that `[f]ailing such a proof, we can certainly have no
rational ground for asserting that one of two alternatives is even
probably right and another wrong'.
As far as I can tell, Moore is not alone and none of these claims has
been established by empirical investigation.
If any of the three claims about the relationship between near and remote consequences is a conceptual claim, it is false. Consider first the claim that remote consequences are insignificant. It would seem that the remote consequences of an act could be more significant than the close ones simply by virtue of there being more. This is true of any act that is part of the beginning of a social, political, religious or scientific movement.
What about the claim that the relative utilities of the near and remote consequences of acts are the same? If this is a conceptual claim, it is a dubious one. It is not hard to imagine that the near consequences of using a certain pesticide to increase the food supply would be very good and the remote consequences very bad, while the near consequences of not using the pesticide would be quite bad and the remote consequences quite good.
Are we justified in believing that, after a time, the good and bad consequences of an act even out? Again, if this is a conceptual claim, it is false. Assume that it is a commonsense view that persons of one sex are mentally inferior to persons of another sex. Also, assume that this view had its roots in one act. It is not hard to imagine that there are many more bad remote consequences of this act than there are good remote consequences of it.
There is one additional strategy which might be employed by a
proponent of any of these views about the relationship between near
and remote consequences. It is suggested by J. J. C. Smart, who says
that we should accept the claim that the remote consequences of
actions are insignificant because they `approximate rapidly to zero
like the furthermost ripples on a pond after a stone has been dropped
into it'. The strategy is to justify
acceptance of the claim on theoretical grounds, namely that if it is
not accepted, then the theory, AU, must be seen as impracticable.
Smart says that assuming it is needed in order `to make utilitarianism
workable in practice'.
Since I am arguing that AU's not being practicable has an interesting
and, perhaps, unhappy consequence, it would be unreasonable for me
simply to accept the truth of this assumption.
This concludes my defence of premise (1). I have considered whether AU can have a practicable, validated EDP and have attempted to establish that it cannot.
Whatever method we use to acquire the relevant evidence would be a
candidate for an EDP. But I have argued that, considered as an EDP,
AU is impracticable, and, given this, no other EDP for AU could be
validated. So there is no method that we can use for acquiring this
evidence and we do not have reasonable grounds for believing that we
ever have it. We cannot, therefore, be justified in believing of any
particular act that it satisfies AU's conditions for moral
permissibility.
If my reasons in support of this conclusion are good, then, it seems,
we have to accept that we are pretty much in the dark about the
relative utilities of all acts.
It might be objected that I am asking too much: where I appear to be asking for justification, I am actually demanding certainty. No one is going to argue that we can be certain about what is morally permissible. Reasonable act utilitarians will say only that we have enough evidence about the utilities of alternatives to make rational decisions about what is morally permissible. Surely this is good enough. Since my argument supposes the stronger claim, which no one makes, it is an argument against a straw man. Call this `the straw man objection'.
According to proponents of this objection, what evidence about utilities allows these decisions to be rational? If the objection is to be successful, evidence about near consequences must suffice. Since evidence about near consequences can provide a preponderance of evidence that an alternative has maximal overall utility, perhaps this is adequate. So it is rational to decide that an alternative is morally permissible when there is a preponderance of evidence that it has maximal utility. If this is correct, it could be rational to choose an alternative solely because of the evidence about its near consequences.
On this view, what are we to say about remote consequences, which, for
all we know, might affect the relative utilities of the alternatives?
Since evidence concerning remote consequences is not available to us,
it cannot be part of our evidence for or against some alternative's
having maximal utility. Consequently, remote consequences can safely
be ignored. They are to be ignored, not because they are irrelevant
to an alternative's utility, but because they are irrelevant to
rational decisions based on a desire to maximize utility.
The result of these considerations is, purportedly, that evidence about the near consequences of alternatives allows us to have beliefs about the overall utilities of alternatives that are sufficiently justified for decisions based on those beliefs to be rational. So, while the beliefs are not certain, they are justified enough to support rational decisions. It is in failing to recognize this that my argument is supposed to miss the mark.
In order to see how the straw man objection fails, we have to distinguish between rational justification for acting and epistemic justification for believing. These two sometimes come apart. We can be rationally justified in doing something, without being epistemically justified in believing that our decision is correct. My claim is not that, if AU is true, we can never be rationally justified in doing something (even on utilitarian grounds). It is that we would not be epistemically justified in believing that our action will maximize utility or is morally right.
To see how rational and epistemic justification can diverge, consider the following. We have a choice between incompatible alternatives, A, B and C. There is a .45 chance of A's being the alternative that maximizes utility, a .35 chance of B's being that alternative and a .20 chance of C's being that alternative. We know these probabilities and that we are trying to maximize utility. It seems that it would be uniquely rational to do A. Do we have good reason to believe that doing A will maximize utility? I think not. We know that the chance of A's maximizing utility is less than the chance of its not doing so: there is a .55 chance that B or C will be the alternative that maximizes utility. So we are rationally justified in doing A, but not epistemically justified in believing that A is the alternative that will maximize utility. Rational justification and epistemic justification can diverge.
I have been arguing that, in general, our available evidence is woefully inadequate to justify belief about the utilities of our alternatives. My strategy has been to try to show that we do not have sufficient reason to believe that evidence about near consequences is adequate when trying to determine relative utility. So, although the evidence that we have might seem to indicate that some alternative has the most utility, this evidence is undermined by our knowledge that we do not have good evidence about the remote consequences of the alternative and that the remote consequences are relevant.
This does not undermine the claim that it is rational to decide what to do based on our knowledge of near consequences. If we have to make a decision, it is rational to act on the best information we have, even if we know that our information is completely inadequate. It is unfortunate, but true, that we often have to make decisions, perhaps rational decisions, with evidence that is insufficient to justify the belief that we have made the correct decision. Indeed, we sometimes have to make decisions knowing that we are likely to be wrong. My view is that, if AU is correct, this is true of moral decisions.
Of course there is some connection between rational and epistemic justification. If moral decisions are rationally justified, but we are not epistemically justified in believing that they will have the results we hope for, that they are rational is of little comfort.
Why might my argument be thought to rely on such a general skepticism? The reasoning might go like this: If induction is justified and we can have justified beliefs about the relative utilities of past acts according to their types, then we can have justified beliefs about the relative utilities of present alternative acts of those types. Your argument rejects the consequent of this conditional, so it rejects the antecedent: either induction is not justified or we cannot have justified beliefs about the relative utilities of past acts according to their types. Since it is reasonable to believe that we can have justified beliefs about the relative utilities of past acts according to their types, you must reject the view that induction is justified. That is, you must accept skepticism with respect to induction and knowledge of the future.
I do reject the antecedent of the conditional, but not, however, its inductive conjunct. Instead, I reject the claim, understood in the proper manner, that we have justified beliefs about the relative utilities of past acts and, therefore, their relative utilities according to type.
Observed or experienced consequences of actions are supposed to provide the base for induction. As time passes, however, the consequences of an act become more and more intermingled with the consequences of other acts; it becomes more and more difficult to apportion responsibility between acts and to know whether and to what degree some event is the consequence of some act. So, considering an earlier example, it is difficult to determine the consequences and relative utilities of Socrates' drinking or not drinking the hemlock. Indeed, it is even likely that most past acts are still having consequences and will do so into the indefinite future. Unless we can discount the consequences of acts from the time that determining them becomes practically impossible, we cannot be in a position to make justified claims about the relative utilities of past acts. And I have argued that we do not have either empirical or conceptual grounds for discounting remote consequences. Consequently, we are not in a position to make justified claims about the overall relative utilities of acts, past or present.
I am not skeptical about induction; rather, I am skeptical about our
ability to have justified beliefs about the overall consequences of
any action. Mill's claim that for `the whole past duration of the
human species ...mankind have been learning by experience the
tendencies of actions' may, on one interpretation, be
true. But it is true only if it is
understood as a claim about the near consequences of actions.
See, for example, J.L. Mackie, Ethics: Inventing
Right and Wrong, Harmondsworth, 1977, p. 129, where he says that even
if problems concerning the calculation of utility were solved `there
would still be a fatal objection to the resulting act utilitarian
system. It would be wholly impracticable'.
See R. Eugene Bales, `Act-Utilitarianism: Account of Right-Making
Characteristics or Decision-Making Procedure?', American
Philosophical Quarterly, viii (1971), 257-265; David O. Brink,
Moral Realism and the Foundations of Ethics, Cambridge,
1989, pp. 256-261; and James Griffin, Well-Being, Oxford,
1986, pp. 195-206.
Peter Railton, `Alienation, Consequentialism and the Demands of
Morality', Philosophy and Public Affairs, xiii (1984), p.
117.
G.E. Moore, Principia Ethica, Cambridge, 1903, is a
utilitarian of the former kind, while, perhaps, Griffin is a
utilitarian of the latter kind.
For an excellent discussion of this strategy and the costs
associated with it see John Broome, Weighing Goods, Oxford,
1991, ch. 5.
For an interesting discussion of the difficulties associated with
specifying a unique set of alternatives see Lars Bergström, `On
the Formulation and Application of Utilitarianism', Nous, x
(1976), 121-144. For a discussion of the problem of determining
utilities of acts whose consequences we know see Griffin, `Part Two:
Measurement', pp. 27-124.
Throughout I am taking it that there is a distinction between an
alternative and its consequences. If alternatives are characterized
in terms of acts and their consequences, then my claim would be that
it is practically impossible to determine our alternatives.
See Jonathan Bennett, Events and Their Names, Indianapolis,
1988, p. 49. For a discussion of the transitivity of causation see
pages 46-49 of the same work.
There is one kind of possible situation that represents an
exception to my claim. It seems that there may be situations where we
are justified in believing that an act and its alternatives will have
no further consequences at all. For example, we might know that the
end of the earth was imminent. This is not our ordinary situation.
Moore, pp. 151-153.
Moore, p. 153.
J.J.C. Smart and Bernard Williams, Utilitarianism:
For and Against, Cambridge, 1973, p. 33.
Smart, p. 34. He concedes that there may be cases where the
remote consequences do not diminish in significance. One such case
would be Adam and Eve's production of offspring. It is not clear
whether he thinks the principle actually is true, or whether he thinks
that we should make our choices as if it were. He does say that he
does not `know how to prove such a postulate, though it seems
plausible enough' (p. 34).
I am assuming that if you do not have good reason for believing
that you are justified in believing a proposition, then you are not
justified in believing the proposition. If this is not acceptable,
then the argument can be modified.
I believe that forms of this argument have been suggested
to me by various philosophers, including Alan Fuchs, Heidi Malm, and
Roger Crisp. Crisp also suggested that this argument can be found in
Moore. In my discussion of discounting I gave what I believe to be a
correct account of Moore's argument. As I see it, Moore recognizes
that our being justified in ignoring remote consequences is
conditional on showing that over a period of time the consequences
become less significant. He gives his reasons for believing that
showing this is possible, but does not claim that he has shown it or
that anyone else has. However, the rest of his discussion assumes
that it has been shown. This, I believe, gives the false appearance
that he is claiming that we can simply ignore remote consequences.
Utilitarianism, ed. John M. Robson, Toronto, 1965,
Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, x. 224.
Versions of this paper were presented at the 1990 meeting
of the Virginia Philosophical Association, the 1991 Pacific Division
meeting of the APA and the Wolfson Philosophical Society (Oxford). I
thank the participants in those meetings for their comments, in
particular Alan Fuchs, Tony Ellis, Roger Crisp and Heidi Malm (who
served as commentator at the APA meeting). Also, I am grateful to
others who have provided comments on various versions of this paper,
especially Brad Hooker, Peter Vallentyne and Penelope Mackie.